HOME
ListMoto - Socrates


--- Advertisement ---



(i) (i) (i) (i)

Socrates
Socrates
(/ˈsɒkrətiːz/;[2] Ancient Greek: Σωκρᾰ́της, translit. Sōkrátēs, [sɔːkrátɛːs]; c. 470 – 399 BC)[3][4] was a classical Greek (Athenian) philosopher credited as one of the founders of Western philosophy, and as being the first moral philosopher,[5][6] of the Western ethical tradition of thought.[7][8][9] An enigmatic figure, he made no writings, and is known chiefly through the accounts of classical writers writing after his lifetime, particularly his students Plato
Plato
and Xenophon. Other sources include the contemporaneous Antisthenes, Aristippus, and Aeschines of Sphettos. Aristophanes, a playwright, is the only source to have written during his lifetime.[10][11] Plato's dialogues are among the most comprehensive accounts of Socrates
Socrates
to survive from antiquity, though it is unclear the degree to which Socrates
Socrates
himself is "hidden behind his 'best disciple'".[12] Through his portrayal in Plato's dialogues, Socrates
Socrates
has become renowned for his contribution to the field of ethics, and it is this Platonic Socrates
Socrates
who lends his name to the concepts of Socratic irony and the Socratic method, or elenchus. The elenchus remains a commonly used tool in a wide range of discussions, and is a type of pedagogy in which a series of questions is asked not only to draw individual answers, but also to encourage fundamental insight into the issue at hand. Plato's Socrates
Socrates
also made important and lasting contributions to the field of epistemology, and his ideologies and approach have proven a strong foundation for much Western philosophy
Western philosophy
that has followed.

Contents

1 Socratic problem

1.1 Socrates
Socrates
as a figure 1.2 Socrates
Socrates
as a philosopher

2 Biography

2.1 Sources 2.2 Early life 2.3 Military service 2.4 Epistates at the trial of the six commanders 2.5 Arrest of Leon 2.6 Trial and death

2.6.1 Causes of the trial 2.6.2 Trial 2.6.3 Death of Socrates

2.6.3.1 Last words 2.6.3.2 Refusal to escape

3 Philosophy

3.1 Socratic method 3.2 Philosophical beliefs 3.3 Socratic paradoxes 3.4 Knowledge 3.5 Virtue 3.6 Politics 3.7 Covertness

4 Satirical playwrights 5 Prose sources

5.1 The Socratic dialogues

6 Legacy

6.1 Immediate influence 6.2 Later historical influence 6.3 Criticism 6.4 In literature

7 See also 8 Notes 9 References 10 External links

Socratic problem Main article: Socratic problem As Socrates
Socrates
did not write down any of his teachings,[13][14] information about him and his philosophies depends upon secondary sources. Furthermore, close comparison between the contents of these sources reveals contradictions, thus creating concerns about the possibility of knowing in-depth the real Socrates. This issue is known as the Socratic problem,[15] or the Socratic question.[16][17] To understand Socrates
Socrates
and his thought, one must turn primarily to the works of Plato, whose dialogues are thought the most informative source about Socrates' life and philosophy,[18] and also Xenophon.[19] These writings are the Sokratikoi logoi, or Socratic dialogues, which consist of reports of conversations apparently involving Socrates.[20][21] As for discovering the real-life Socrates, the difficulty is that ancient sources are mostly philosophical or dramatic texts, apart from Xenophon. There are no straightforward histories, contemporary with Socrates, that dealt with his own time and place. A corollary of this is that sources that do mention Socrates
Socrates
do not necessarily claim to be historically accurate, and are often partisan. For instance, those who prosecuted and convicted Socrates
Socrates
have left no testament. Historians therefore face the challenge of reconciling the various evidence from the extant texts in order to attempt an accurate and consistent account of Socrates' life and work. The result of such an effort is not necessarily realistic, even if consistent. Two factors emerge from all sources pertaining to the character of Socrates: that he was ugly, and had a brilliant intellect.[22][23] He lived entirely within ancient Athens, he made no writings,[24] and died of execution by hemlock.[25] Socrates
Socrates
as a figure The character of Socrates
Socrates
as exhibited in Apology, Crito, Phaedo
Phaedo
and Symposium concurs with other sources to an extent to which it seems possible to rely on the Platonic Socrates, as demonstrated in the dialogues, as a representation of the actual Socrates
Socrates
as he lived in history.[26] At the same time, however, many scholars believe that in some works, Plato, being a literary artist, pushed his avowedly brightened-up version of "Socrates" far beyond anything the historical Socrates
Socrates
was likely to have done or said. Also, Xenophon, being an historian, is a more reliable witness to the historical Socrates. It is a matter of much debate over which Socrates
Socrates
it is whom Plato
Plato
is describing at any given point—the historical figure, or Plato's fictionalization. As British philosopher Martin Cohen has put it, "Plato, the idealist, offers an idol, a master figure, for philosophy. A Saint, a prophet of 'the Sun-God', a teacher condemned for his teachings as a heretic."[27] It is also clear from other writings and historical artefacts, that Socrates
Socrates
was not simply a character, nor an invention, of Plato. The testimony of Xenophon
Xenophon
and Aristotle, alongside some of Aristophanes' work (especially The Clouds), is useful in fleshing out a perception of Socrates
Socrates
beyond Plato's work. According to one source, the name Σωκρᾰ́της (Sōkrátēs), has the meaning "whole, unwounded, safe" (the part of the name corresponding to σῶς, sôs) and "power" (the part of the name corresponding to κράτος, krátos).[28][29] Socrates
Socrates
as a philosopher The problem with discerning Socrates' philosophical views stems from the perception of contradictions in statements made by the Socrates
Socrates
in the different dialogues of Plato; and in later dialogues Plato
Plato
used the character Socrates
Socrates
to give voice to views that were his own. These contradictions produce doubt as to the actual philosophical doctrines of Socrates, within his milieu and as recorded by other individuals.[30] Aristotle, in his Magna Moralia, refers to Socrates in words which make it patent that the doctrine virtue is knowledge was held by Socrates. Within the Metaphysics, he states Socrates
Socrates
was occupied with the search for moral virtues, being the "first to search for universal definitions for them".[31] The problem of understanding Socrates
Socrates
as a philosopher is shown in the following: In Xenophon's Symposium, Socrates
Socrates
is reported as saying he devotes himself only to what he regards as the most important art or occupation, that of discussing philosophy. However, in The Clouds, Aristophanes
Aristophanes
portrays Socrates
Socrates
as accepting payment for teaching and running a Sophist school with Chaerephon. Also, in Plato's Apology and Symposium, as well as in Xenophon's accounts, Socrates
Socrates
explicitly denies accepting payment for teaching. More specifically, in the Apology, Socrates
Socrates
cites his poverty as proof that he is not a teacher.

Socrates
Socrates
Tears Alcibiades
Alcibiades
from the Embrace of Sensual Pleasure by Jean-Baptiste Regnault
Jean-Baptiste Regnault
(1791)

Two fragments are extant of the writings by Timon of Phlius
Timon of Phlius
pertaining to Socrates,[32] although Timon is known to have written to ridicule and lampoon philosophy.[33][34] Biography

Socrates
Socrates
and Alcibiades, by Christoffer Wilhelm Eckersberg

Carnelian
Carnelian
gem imprint representing Socrates, Rome, 1st century BC-1st century AD.

Sources Details about the life of Socrates
Socrates
are derived from both contemporary sources, and later ancient period sources. Of the contemporary sources, the greater extent of information is taken from the dialogues of Plato
Plato
and Xenophon
Xenophon
(both devotees of Socrates), and the testaments of Antisthenes, Aristippus, and Aeschines of Sphettos, and the lesser[24] from the plays of Aristophanes.[35] Later ancient period sources include Apollodorus of Athens[36][37] (alive during the second century BC),[38][39] Cicero[24] (alive 106–43 BC),[40] and Diogenes
Diogenes
Laërtius[41] (alive probably in the earlier half of the third century AD).[42] The sources are thought to have in part or wholly made use of the factual information of the life of Socrates
Socrates
available to each of them, to give their own interpretation of the nature of his teaching, giving rise to differing versions in each case. For example,[24] in Aristophanes' play The Clouds, Socrates
Socrates
is made into a clown of sorts, particularly inclined toward sophistry, who teaches his students how to bamboozle their way out of debt. However, since most of Aristophanes' works function as parodies, it is presumed that his characterization in this play was also not literal.[43] In Phaedo, which is the only attested source describing the death of Socrates, Plato
Plato
is thought to have selected and omitted details to provide material for his argument for the existence of the liberation of the soul from the body,[44] an argument he possessed from learning of the ideas of Pythagoras[45] (born sometime after 606 and died sometime after 510 BC).[46][47][48][49] Early life The year of birth of Socrates
Socrates
stated is an assumed date,[50] or estimate,[51] given the fact of the dating of anything in ancient history in part being sometimes reliant on argument stemming from the inexact period floruit of individuals.[52] Diogenes Laërtius
Diogenes Laërtius
stated Socrates
Socrates
birth date was "the sixth day of Thargelion, the day when the Athenians purify the city".[53] Contemporaneous sources state, he was born not very much later than sometime after the year 471,[54] his date of birth is within the period of years ranging 470 to 469 BC,[55] or within a range 469 to 468 BC (corresponding to the fourth year of the 77th Olympiad).[36][37] Socrates
Socrates
was born in Alopeke, and belonged to the tribe Antiochis. His father was Sophroniscus, a sculptor, or stonemason.[56][57][58] His mother was a midwife named Phaenarete.[59] Socrates
Socrates
married Xanthippe, who is especially remembered for having an undesirable temperament.[60] She bore for him three sons,[61] Lamprocles, Sophroniscus and Menexenus. Socrates
Socrates
first worked as a stonemason, and there was a tradition in antiquity, not credited by modern scholarship, that Socrates
Socrates
crafted the statues of the Charites, which stood near the Acropolis until the 2nd century AD.[62] Xenophon
Xenophon
reports that because youths were not allowed to enter the Agora, they used to gather in workshops surrounding it.[63] Socrates frequented these shops in order to converse with the merchants. Most notable among them was Simon the Shoemaker.[64] Military service For a time, Socrates
Socrates
fulfilled the role of hoplite, participating in the Peloponnesian War—a conflict which stretched intermittently over a period spanning 431 to 404 BC.[65] Several of Plato's dialogues refer to Socrates' military service. In the monologue of the Apology, Socrates
Socrates
states he was active for Athens
Athens
in the battles of Amphipolis, Delium, and Potidaea.[66] In the Symposium, Alcibiades
Alcibiades
describes Socrates' valour in the battles of Potidaea and Delium, recounting how Socrates
Socrates
saved his life in the former battle (219e–221b). Socrates' exceptional service at Delium is also mentioned in the Laches by the General after whom the dialogue is named (181b). In the Apology, Socrates
Socrates
compares his military service to his courtroom troubles, and says anyone on the jury who thinks he ought to retreat from philosophy must also think soldiers should retreat when it seems likely that they will be killed in battle.[67] Epistates at the trial of the six commanders Further information: Battle of Arginusae
Battle of Arginusae
§ Trial of the generals During 406, he participated as a member of the Boule.[68] His tribe the Antiochis held the Prytany on the day it was debated what fate should befall the generals of the Battle of Arginusae, who abandoned the slain and the survivors of foundered ships to pursue the defeated Spartan navy.[57][69][70] According to Xenophon, Socrates
Socrates
was the Epistates for the debate,[71] but Delebecque and Hatzfeld think this is an embellishment, because Xenophon
Xenophon
composed the information after Socrates' death.[72] The generals were seen by some to have failed to uphold the most basic of duties, and the people decided upon capital punishment. However, when the prytany responded by refusing to vote on the issue, the people reacted with threats of death directed at the prytany itself. They relented, at which point Socrates
Socrates
alone as epistates blocked the vote, which had been proposed by Callixeinus.[73][74] The reason he gave was that "in no case would he act except in accordance with the law".[75] The outcome of the trial was ultimately judged to be a miscarriage of justice, or illegal, but, actually, Socrates' decision had no support from written statutory law, instead being reliant on favouring a continuation of less strict and less formal nomos law.[74][76][77] Arrest of Leon Plato's Apology, parts 32c to 32d, describes how Socrates
Socrates
and four others were summoned to the Tholos, and told by representatives of the oligarchy of the Thirty (the oligarchy began ruling in 404 BC) to go to Salamis, and from there, to return to them with Leon the Salaminian. He was to be brought back to be subsequently executed. However, Socrates
Socrates
returned home and did not go to Salamis as he was expected to.[78][79] Trial and death Causes of the trial Socrates
Socrates
lived during the time of the transition from the height of the Athenian hegemony to its decline with the defeat by Sparta
Sparta
and its allies in the Peloponnesian War. At a time when Athens
Athens
sought to stabilize and recover from its defeat, the Athenian public may have been entertaining doubts about democracy as an efficient form of government. Socrates
Socrates
appears to have been a critic of democracy,[80] and some scholars interpret his trial as an expression of political infighting.[81]

The Death of Socrates, by Jacques-Louis David
Jacques-Louis David
(1787)

Claiming loyalty to his city, Socrates
Socrates
clashed with the current course of Athenian politics and society.[82] He praised Sparta, archrival to Athens, directly and indirectly in various dialogues. One of Socrates' purported offenses to the city was his position as a social and moral critic. Rather than upholding a status quo and accepting the development of what he perceived as immorality within his region, Socrates
Socrates
questioned the collective notion of "might makes right" that he felt was common in Greece during this period. Plato
Plato
refers to Socrates
Socrates
as the "gadfly" of the state (as the gadfly stings the horse into action, so Socrates
Socrates
stung various Athenians), insofar as he irritated some people with considerations of justice and the pursuit of goodness.[83] His attempts to improve the Athenians' sense of justice may have been the cause of his execution. According to Plato's Apology, Socrates' life as the "gadfly" of Athens began when his friend Chaerephon asked the oracle at Delphi
Delphi
if anyone were wiser than Socrates; the Oracle
Oracle
responded that no-one was wiser. Socrates
Socrates
believed the Oracle's response was not correct, because he believed he possessed no wisdom whatsoever. He proceeded to test the riddle by approaching men considered wise by the people of Athens—statesmen, poets, and artisans—in order to refute the Oracle's pronouncement. Questioning them, however, Socrates
Socrates
concluded: while each man thought he knew a great deal and was wise, in fact they knew very little and were not wise at all. Socrates
Socrates
realized the Oracle
Oracle
was correct; while so-called wise men thought themselves wise and yet were not, he himself knew he was not wise at all, which, paradoxically, made him the wiser one since he was the only person aware of his own ignorance. Socrates' paradoxical wisdom made the prominent Athenians he publicly questioned look foolish, turning them against him and leading to accusations of wrongdoing. Socrates defended his role as a gadfly until the end: at his trial, when Socrates
Socrates
was asked to propose his own punishment, he suggested a wage paid by the government and free dinners for the rest of his life instead, to finance the time he spent as Athens' benefactor.[84] Robin Waterfield suggests that Socrates
Socrates
was a voluntary scapegoat; his death was the purifying remedy for Athens' misfortunes. In this view, the token of appreciation for Asclepius
Asclepius
(the Greek god for curing illness) would represent a cure for Athens' ailments.[83] Trial Main article: Trial of Socrates One day during the year 399 BC, Socrates
Socrates
went on trial[85] and was subsequently found guilty of both corrupting the minds of the youth of Athens
Athens
and of impiety (asebeia,[86] "not believing in the gods of the state"),[87] and as a punishment sentenced to death, caused by the drinking of a mixture containing poison hemlock.[88][89][90][91]

Bust of Socrates
Socrates
in the Vatican Museum

Death of Socrates Socrates' death is described at the end of Plato's Phaedo, although Plato
Plato
was not himself present at the execution. As to the veracity of Plato's account it seems possible he made choice of a number of certain factors perhaps omitting others in the description of the death, as the Phaedo
Phaedo
description does not describe progress of the action of the poison (Gill 1973) in concurrence with modern descriptions.[92] Phaedo
Phaedo
states, after drinking the poison, he was instructed to walk around until his legs felt numb. After he lay down, the man who administered the poison pinched his foot; Socrates
Socrates
could no longer feel his legs. The numbness slowly crept up his body until it reached his heart. Socrates
Socrates
chose to cover his face during the execution (118 a6 Phaedo).[93] According to Phaedo
Phaedo
(61c–69e),[94] Socrates
Socrates
states that "[a]ll of philosophy is training for death".[95][96] Last words Socrates
Socrates
last words are thought to be ironic (C. Gill 1973),[44] or sincere (J. Crooks 1998).[97] Socrates
Socrates
speaks his last words to Crito (depending on the translation):

Crito, we owe a rooster to Asclepius. Please, don't forget to pay the debt.[98]

or

"Crito, we owe a cock to Asclepius, Pay it and do not neglect it.[97]

or

Crito, we owe a cock to Asclepius, make this offering to him and do not forget.[99]

Refusal to escape Socrates
Socrates
turned down Crito's pleas to attempt an escape from prison. Xenophon
Xenophon
and Plato
Plato
agree that Socrates
Socrates
had an opportunity to escape, as his followers were able to bribe the prison guards. There have been several suggestions offered as reasons why he chose to stay:

He believed such a flight would indicate a fear of death, which he believed no true philosopher has. If he fled Athens
Athens
his teaching would fare no better in another country, as he would continue questioning all he met and undoubtedly incur their displeasure. Having knowingly agreed to live under the city's laws, he implicitly subjected himself to the possibility of being accused of crimes by its citizens and judged guilty by its jury. To do otherwise would have caused him to break his "social contract" with the state, and so harm the state, an unprincipled act. If he escaped at the instigation of his friends, then his friends would become liable in law.[100]

The full reasoning behind his refusal to flee is the main subject of the Crito.[101][102] In as much as Socrates
Socrates
drank hemlock willingly without complaint (having decided against fleeing), R.G. Frey (1978) has suggested in truth, Socrates
Socrates
chose to commit suicide.[103][104] Philosophy

Part of a series on

Plato

Plato
Plato
from Raphael's The School of Athens
Athens
(1509–1511)

Early life Works Platonism Epistemology Idealism / realism Demiurge Theory of forms Theory of soul Transcendentals Form of the Good Third man argument Euthyphro
Euthyphro
dilemma Five regimes Philosopher
Philosopher
king Plato's unwritten doctrines political philosophy

Allegories and metaphors

Atlantis Ring of Gyges The Cave The Divided Line The Sun Ship of State Myth of Er The Chariot

Related articles

Commentaries The Academy
Academy
in Athens Socratic problem Middle Platonism Neoplatonism

and Christianity

Allegorical interpretations of Plato Socratic fallacy

Philosophy
Philosophy
portal

v t e

Socratic method Main article: Socratic method Perhaps his most important contribution to Western thought is his dialectic method of inquiry, known as the Socratic method
Socratic method
or method of "elenchus", which he largely applied to the examination of key moral concepts such as the Good and Justice. It was first described by Plato in the Socratic Dialogues. To solve a problem, it would be broken down into a series of questions, the answers to which gradually distill the answer a person would seek. The development and practice of this method is one of Socrates' most enduring contributions, and is a key factor in earning his mantle as the father of political philosophy, ethics or moral philosophy, and as a figurehead of all the central themes in Western philosophy. The Socratic method
Socratic method
has often been considered as a defining element of American legal education.[105] To illustrate the use of the Socratic method, a series of questions are posed to help a person or group to determine their underlying beliefs and the extent of their knowledge. The Socratic method
Socratic method
is a negative method of hypothesis elimination, in that better hypotheses are found by steadily identifying and eliminating those that lead to contradictions. It was designed to force one to examine one's own beliefs and the validity of such beliefs. An alternative interpretation of the dialectic is that it is a method for direct perception of the Form of the Good. Philosopher
Philosopher
Karl Popper describes the dialectic as "the art of intellectual intuition, of visualising the divine originals, the Forms or Ideas, of unveiling the Great Mystery behind the common man's everyday world of appearances."[106] In a similar vein, French philosopher Pierre Hadot suggests that the dialogues are a type of spiritual exercise. Hadot writes that "in Plato's view, every dialectical exercise, precisely because it is an exercise of pure thought, subject to the demands of the Logos, turns the soul away from the sensible world, and allows it to convert itself towards the Good."[107] Philosophical beliefs The beliefs of Socrates, as distinct from those of Plato, are difficult to discern. Little in the way of concrete evidence exists to demarcate the two. The lengthy presentation of ideas given in most of the dialogues may be the ideas of Socrates
Socrates
himself, but which have been subsequently deformed or changed by Plato, and some scholars think Plato
Plato
so adapted the Socratic style as to make the literary character and the philosopher himself impossible to distinguish. Others argue that he did have his own theories and beliefs.[108] There is a degree of controversy inherent in the identifying of what these might have been, owing to the difficulty of separating Socrates
Socrates
from Plato
Plato
and the difficulty of interpreting even the dramatic writings concerning Socrates. Consequently, distinguishing the philosophical beliefs of Socrates
Socrates
from those of Plato
Plato
and Xenophon
Xenophon
has not proven easy, so it must be remembered that what is attributed to Socrates might actually be more the specific concerns of these two thinkers instead. The matter is complicated because the historical Socrates
Socrates
seems to have been notorious for asking questions but not answering, claiming to lack wisdom concerning the subjects about which he questioned others.[109] If anything in general can be said about the philosophical beliefs of Socrates, it is that he was morally, intellectually, and politically at odds with many of his fellow Athenians. When he is on trial for heresy and corrupting the minds of the youth of Athens, he uses his method of elenchos to demonstrate to the jurors that their moral values are wrong-headed. He tells them they are concerned with their families, careers, and political responsibilities when they ought to be worried about the "welfare of their souls". Socrates' assertion that the gods had singled him out as a divine emissary seemed to provoke irritation, if not outright ridicule. Socrates
Socrates
also questioned the Sophistic doctrine that arete (virtue) can be taught. He liked to observe that successful fathers (such as the prominent military general Pericles) did not produce sons of their own quality. Socrates argued that moral excellence was more a matter of divine bequest than parental nurture. This belief may have contributed to his lack of anxiety about the future of his own sons. Also, according to A. A. Long, "There should be no doubt that, despite his claim to know only that he knew nothing, Socrates
Socrates
had strong beliefs about the divine", and, citing Xenophon's Memorabilia, 1.4, 4.3,:

According to Xenophon, he was a teleologist who held that god arranges everything for the best.[110]

Socrates
Socrates
frequently says his ideas are not his own, but his teachers'. He mentions several influences: Prodicus
Prodicus
the rhetor and Anaxagoras
Anaxagoras
the philosopher. Perhaps surprisingly, Socrates
Socrates
claims to have been deeply influenced by two women besides his mother: he says that Diotima (cf. Plato's Symposium), a witch and priestess from Mantinea, taught him all he knows about eros, or love; and that Aspasia, the mistress of Pericles, taught him the art of rhetoric.[111] John Burnet argued that his principal teacher was the Anaxagorean Archelaus but his ideas were as Plato
Plato
described them; Eric A. Havelock, on the other hand, did not accept the view that Socrates' view was identical with that of Archelaus, in large part due to the reason of such anomalies and contradictions that have surfaced and "post-dated his death."[112] Socratic paradoxes Many of the beliefs traditionally attributed to the historical Socrates
Socrates
have been characterized as "paradoxical" because they seem to conflict with common sense. The following are among the so-called Socratic paradoxes:[113]

No one desires evil. No one errs or does wrong willingly or knowingly. Virtue—all virtue—is knowledge. Virtue is sufficient for happiness.

The term, "Socratic paradox" can also refer to a self-referential paradox, originating in Socrates' utterance, "what I do not know I do not think I know",[114] often paraphrased as "I know that I know nothing." Knowledge The statement "I know that I know nothing" is often attributed to Socrates, based on a statement in Plato's Apology.[115] The conventional interpretation of this is that Socrates' wisdom was limited to an awareness of his own ignorance. Socrates
Socrates
considered virtuousness to require or consist of phronēsis, "thought, sense, judgement, practical wisdom, [and] prudence."[116][117] Therefore, he believed that wrongdoing and behaviour that was not virtuous resulted from ignorance, and that those who did wrong knew no better.[118] The one thing Socrates
Socrates
claimed to have knowledge of was "the art of love" (ta erôtikê). This assertion seems to be associated with the word erôtan, which means to ask questions. Therefore, Socrates
Socrates
is claiming to know about the art of love, insofar as he knows how to ask questions.[119][120] The only time he actually claimed to be wise was within Apology, in which he says he is wise "in the limited sense of having human wisdom".[121] It is debatable whether Socrates
Socrates
believed humans (as opposed to gods like Apollo) could actually become wise. On the one hand, he drew a clear line between human ignorance and ideal knowledge; on the other, Plato's Symposium (Diotima's Speech) and Republic (Allegory of the Cave) describe a method for ascending to wisdom. In Plato's Theaetetus (150a), Socrates
Socrates
compares his treatment of the young people who come to him for philosophical advice to the way midwives treat their patients, and the way matrimonial matchmakers act. He says that he himself is a true matchmaker (προμνηστικός promnestikós) in that he matches the young man to the best philosopher for his particular mind. However, he carefully distinguishes himself from a panderer (προᾰγωγός proagogos) or procurer. This distinction is echoed in Xenophon's Symposium (3.20), when Socrates
Socrates
jokes about his certainty of being able to make a fortune, if he chose to practice the art of pandering. For his part as a philosophical interlocutor, he leads his respondent to a clearer conception of wisdom, although he claims he is not himself a teacher (Apology). His role, he claims, is more properly to be understood as analogous to a midwife (μαῖα maia).[122][123] In the Theaetetus, Socrates
Socrates
explains that he is himself barren of theories, but knows how to bring the theories of others to birth and determine whether they are worthy or mere "wind eggs" (ἀνεμιαῖον anemiaion). Perhaps significantly, he points out that midwives are barren due to age, and women who have never given birth are unable to become midwives; they would have no experience or knowledge of birth and would be unable to separate the worthy infants from those that should be left on the hillside to be exposed. To judge this, the midwife must have experience and knowledge of what she is judging.[124][125] Virtue

Bust of Socrates
Socrates
in the Palermo Archaeological Museum

Socrates
Socrates
believed the best way for people to live was to focus on the pursuit of virtue rather than the pursuit, for instance, of material wealth.[126] He always invited others to try to concentrate more on friendships and a sense of true community, for Socrates
Socrates
felt this was the best way for people to grow together as a populace.[127] His actions lived up to this standard: in the end, Socrates
Socrates
accepted his death sentence when most thought he would simply leave Athens, as he felt he could not run away from or go against the will of his community; as mentioned above, his reputation for valor on the battlefield was without reproach. The idea that there are certain virtues formed a common thread in Socrates' teachings. These virtues represented the most important qualities for a person to have, foremost of which were the philosophical or intellectual virtues. Socrates
Socrates
stressed that "the unexamined life is not worth living [and] ethical virtue is the only thing that matters."[128] Politics It is argued that Socrates
Socrates
believed "ideals belong in a world only the wise man can understand",[129] making the philosopher the only type of person suitable to govern others. In Plato's dialogue the Republic, Socrates
Socrates
openly objected to the democracy that ran Athens
Athens
during his adult life. It was not only Athenian democracy: Socrates
Socrates
found short of ideal any government that did not conform to his presentation of a perfect regime led by philosophers, and Athenian government was far from that. It is, however, possible that the Socrates
Socrates
of Plato's Republic is colored by Plato's own views. During the last years of Socrates' life, Athens
Athens
was in continual flux due to political upheaval. Democracy
Democracy
was at last overthrown by a junta known as the Thirty Tyrants, led by Plato's relative, Critias, who had once been a student and friend of Socrates. The Tyrants ruled for about a year before the Athenian democracy
Athenian democracy
was reinstated, at which point it declared an amnesty for all recent events. Socrates' opposition to democracy is often denied, and the question is one of the biggest philosophical debates when trying to determine exactly what Socrates
Socrates
believed. The strongest argument of those who claim Socrates
Socrates
did not actually believe in the idea of philosopher kings is that the view is expressed no earlier than Plato's Republic, which is widely considered one of Plato's "Middle" dialogues and not representative of the historical Socrates' views. Furthermore, according to Plato's Apology of Socrates, an "early" dialogue, Socrates
Socrates
refused to pursue conventional politics; he often stated he could not look into other's matters or tell people how to live their lives when he did not yet understand how to live his own. He believed he was a philosopher engaged in the pursuit of Truth, and did not claim to know it fully. Socrates' acceptance of his death sentence after his conviction can also be seen to support this view. It is often claimed much of the anti-democratic leanings are from Plato, who was never able to overcome his disgust at what was done to his teacher. In any case, it is clear Socrates
Socrates
thought the rule of the Thirty Tyrants was also objectionable; when called before them to assist in the arrest of a fellow Athenian, Socrates
Socrates
refused and narrowly escaped death before the Tyrants were overthrown. He did, however, fulfill his duty to serve as Prytanis when a trial of a group of Generals who presided over a disastrous naval campaign were judged; even then, he maintained an uncompromising attitude, being one of those who refused to proceed in a manner not supported by the laws, despite intense pressure.[130] Judging by his actions, he considered the rule of the Thirty Tyrants less legitimate than the Democratic Senate that sentenced him to death. Socrates' apparent respect for democracy is one of the themes emphasized in the 2008 play Socrates on Trial
Socrates on Trial
by Andrew David Irvine. Irvine argues that it was because of his loyalty to Athenian democracy that Socrates
Socrates
was willing to accept the verdict of his fellow citizens. As Irvine puts it, "During a time of war and great social and intellectual upheaval, Socrates
Socrates
felt compelled to express his views openly, regardless of the consequences. As a result, he is remembered today, not only for his sharp wit and high ethical standards, but also for his loyalty to the view that in a democracy the best way for a man to serve himself, his friends, and his city—even during times of war—is by being loyal to, and by speaking publicly about, the truth."[131] Covertness In the Dialogues of Plato, though Socrates
Socrates
sometimes seems to support a mystical side, discussing reincarnation and the mystery religions, this is generally attributed to Plato.[132] Regardless, this view of Socrates
Socrates
cannot be dismissed out of hand, as we cannot be sure of the differences between the views of Plato
Plato
and Socrates; in addition, there seem to be some corollaries in the works of Xenophon. In the culmination of the philosophic path as discussed in Plato's Symposium, one comes to the Sea of Beauty or to the sight of "the beautiful itself" (211C); only then can one become wise. (In the Symposium, Socrates
Socrates
credits his speech on the philosophic path to his teacher, the priestess Diotima, who is not even sure if Socrates
Socrates
is capable of reaching the highest mysteries.) In the Meno, he refers to the Eleusinian Mysteries, telling Meno
Meno
he would understand Socrates' answers better if only he could stay for the initiations next week. Further confusions result from the nature of these sources, insofar as the Platonic Dialogues are arguably the work of an artist-philosopher, whose meaning does not volunteer itself to the passive reader nor again the lifelong scholar. According to Olympiodorus the Younger in his Life of Plato,[133] Plato
Plato
himself "received instruction from the writers of tragedy" before taking up the study of philosophy. His works are, indeed, dialogues; Plato's choice of this, the medium of Sophocles, Euripides, and the fictions of theatre, may reflect the ever-interpretable nature of his writings, as he has been called a "dramatist of reason". What is more, the first word of nearly all Plato's works is a significant term for that respective dialogue, and is used with its many connotations in mind. Finally, the Phaedrus and the Symposium each allude to Socrates' coy delivery of philosophic truths in conversation; the Socrates
Socrates
of the Phaedrus goes so far as to demand such dissembling and mystery in all writing. The covertness we often find in Plato, appearing here and there couched in some enigmatic use of symbol and/or irony, may be at odds with the mysticism Plato's Socrates
Socrates
expounds in some other dialogues. These indirect methods may fail to satisfy some readers. Perhaps the most interesting facet of this is Socrates' reliance on what the Greeks called his "daimōnic sign", an averting (ἀποτρεπτικός apotreptikos) inner voice Socrates
Socrates
heard only when he was about to make a mistake. It was this sign that prevented Socrates
Socrates
from entering into politics. In the Phaedrus, we are told Socrates
Socrates
considered this to be a form of "divine madness", the sort of insanity that is a gift from the gods and gives us poetry, mysticism, love, and even philosophy itself. Alternately, the sign is often taken to be what we would call "intuition"; however, Socrates' characterization of the phenomenon as daimōnic may suggest that its origin is divine, mysterious, and independent of his own thoughts. Today, such a voice would be classified under the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders as a command hallucination.[134] Socrates
Socrates
practiced and advocated divination.[135] Xenophon
Xenophon
was thought skilled at foretelling from sacrifices, and attributed many of his knowledges to Socrates
Socrates
within his writing "The Cavalry Commander".[135] Satirical playwrights He was prominently lampooned in Aristophanes' comedy The Clouds, produced when Socrates
Socrates
was in his mid-forties; he said at his trial (according to Plato) that the laughter of the theater was a harder task to answer than the arguments of his accusers. Søren Kierkegaard believed this play was a more accurate representation of Socrates
Socrates
than those of his students. In the play, Socrates
Socrates
is ridiculed for his dirtiness, which is associated with the Laconizing fad; also in plays by Callias, Eupolis, and Telecleides. Other comic poets who lampooned Socrates
Socrates
include Mnesimachus and Ameipsias. In all of these, Socrates and the Sophists were criticized for "the moral dangers inherent in contemporary thought and literature". Prose sources Plato, Xenophon, and Aristotle
Aristotle
are the main sources for the historical Socrates; however, Xenophon
Xenophon
and Plato
Plato
were students of Socrates, and they may idealize him; however, they wrote the only extended descriptions of Socrates
Socrates
that have come down to us in their complete form. Aristotle
Aristotle
refers frequently, but in passing, to Socrates
Socrates
in his writings. Almost all of Plato's works center on Socrates. However, Plato's later works appear to be more his own philosophy put into the mouth of his mentor. The Socratic dialogues Main article: Socratic dialogue The Socratic Dialogues are a series of dialogues written by Plato
Plato
and Xenophon
Xenophon
in the form of discussions between Socrates
Socrates
and other persons of his time, or as discussions between Socrates' followers over his concepts. Plato's Phaedo
Phaedo
is an example of this latter category. Although his Apology is a monologue delivered by Socrates, it is usually grouped with the Dialogues. The Apology professes to be a record of the actual speech Socrates delivered in his own defense at the trial. In the Athenian jury system, an "apology" is composed of three parts: a speech, followed by a counter-assessment, then some final words. "Apology" is an anglicized transliteration, not a translation, of the Greek apologia, meaning "defense"; in this sense it is not apologetic according to our contemporary use of the term. Plato
Plato
generally does not place his own ideas in the mouth of a specific speaker; he lets ideas emerge via the Socratic Method, under the guidance of Socrates. Most of the dialogues present Socrates applying this method to some extent, but nowhere as completely as in the Euthyphro. In this dialogue, Socrates
Socrates
and Euthyphro
Euthyphro
go through several iterations of refining the answer to Socrates' question, "...What is the pious, and what the impious?" In Plato's Dialogues, learning appears as a process of remembering. The soul, before its incarnation in the body, was in the realm of Ideas (very similar to the Platonic "Forms"). There, it saw things the way they truly are, rather than the pale shadows or copies we experience on earth. By a process of questioning, the soul can be brought to remember the ideas in their pure form, thus bringing wisdom.[136] Especially for Plato's writings referring to Socrates, it is not always clear which ideas brought forward by Socrates
Socrates
(or his friends) actually belonged to Socrates
Socrates
and which of these may have been new additions or elaborations by Plato—this is known as the Socratic Problem. Generally, the early works of Plato
Plato
are considered to be close to the spirit of Socrates, whereas the later works—including Phaedo
Phaedo
and Republic—are considered to be possibly products of Plato's elaborations.[137] Legacy Immediate influence

Statue of Socrates
Socrates
in front of the Academy
Academy
of Athens
Athens
(modern)

See also: Cyrenaics Immediately, the students of Socrates
Socrates
set to work both on exercising their perceptions of his teachings in politics and also on developing many new philosophical schools of thought. Some of Athens' controversial and anti-democratic tyrants were contemporary or posthumous students of Socrates
Socrates
including Alcibiades
Alcibiades
and Critias. Critias' cousin Plato
Plato
would go on to found the Academy
Academy
in 385 BC, which gained so much renown that "Academy" became the standard word for educational institutions in later European languages such as English, French, and Italian.[138] Plato's protégé, another important figure of the Classical era, Aristotle
Aristotle
went on to tutor Alexander the Great
Alexander the Great
and also to found his own school in 335 BC—the Lyceum—whose name also now means an educational institution.[139] While " Socrates
Socrates
dealt with moral matters and took no notice at all of nature in general",[140] in his Dialogues, Plato
Plato
would emphasize mathematics with metaphysical overtones mirroring that of Pythagoras—the former who would dominate Western thought well into the Renaissance. Aristotle
Aristotle
himself was as much of a philosopher as he was a scientist with extensive work in the fields of biology and physics. Socratic thought which challenged conventions, especially in stressing a simplistic way of living, became divorced from Plato's more detached and philosophical pursuits. This idea was inherited by one of Socrates' older students, Antisthenes, who became the originator of another philosophy in the years after Socrates' death: Cynicism. The idea of asceticism being hand in hand with an ethical life or one with piety, ignored by Plato
Plato
and Aristotle
Aristotle
and somewhat dealt with by the Cynics, formed the core of another philosophy in 281 BC— Stoicism
Stoicism
when Zeno of Citium
Zeno of Citium
would discover Socrates' works and then learn from Crates, a Cynic philosopher.[141] Later historical influence

Depiction of Socrates
Socrates
by 13th century Seljuk illustrator

While some of the later contributions of Socrates
Socrates
to Hellenistic Era culture and philosophy as well as the Roman Era
Roman Era
have been lost to time, his teachings began a resurgence in both medieval Europe and the Islamic Middle East alongside those of Aristotle
Aristotle
and Stoicism. Socrates
Socrates
is mentioned in the dialogue Kuzari
Kuzari
by Jewish philosopher and rabbi Yehuda Halevi
Yehuda Halevi
in which a Jew instructs the Khazar
Khazar
king about Judaism.[142] Al-Kindi, a well-known Arabic philosopher, introduced and tried to reconcile Socrates
Socrates
and Hellenistic philosophy
Hellenistic philosophy
to an Islamic audience,[143] referring to him by the name 'Suqrat'. Socrates' stature in Western philosophy
Western philosophy
returned in full force with the Renaissance
Renaissance
and the Age of Reason in Europe when political theory began to resurface under those like Locke and Hobbes.[144] Voltaire even went so far as to write a satirical play about the trial of Socrates. There were a number of paintings about his life including Socrates
Socrates
Tears Alcibiades
Alcibiades
from the Embrace of Sensual Pleasure by Jean-Baptiste Regnault
Jean-Baptiste Regnault
and The Death of Socrates
The Death of Socrates
by Jacques-Louis David in the later 18th century. To this day, different versions of the Socratic method
Socratic method
are still used in classroom and law school discourse to expose underlying issues in both subject and the speaker. He has been recognized with accolades ranging from frequent mentions in pop culture (such as the movie Bill & Ted's Excellent Adventure and a Greek rock band called Socrates Drank the Conium) to numerous busts in academic institutions in recognition of his contribution to education. Over the past century, numerous plays about Socrates
Socrates
have also focused on Socrates' life and influence. One of the most recent has been Socrates
Socrates
on Trial, a play based on Aristophanes' Clouds and Plato's Apology, Crito, and Phaedo, all adapted for modern performance. Criticism Evaluation of and reaction to Socrates
Socrates
has been undertaken by both historians and philosophers from the time of his death to the present day with a multitude of conclusions and perspectives. Although he was not directly prosecuted for his connection to Critias, leader of the Spartan-backed Thirty Tyrants, and "showed considerable personal courage in refusing to submit to [them]", he was seen by some as a figure who mentored oligarchs who became abusive tyrants, and undermined Athenian democracy. The Sophistic movement that he railed at in life survived him, but by the 3rd century BC, was rapidly overtaken by the many philosophical schools of thought that Socrates influenced.[145] Socrates' death is considered iconic and his status as a martyr of philosophy overshadows most contemporary and posthumous criticism. However, Xenophon
Xenophon
mentions Socrates' "arrogance" and that he was "an expert in the art of primping" or "self-presentation".[146] Direct criticism of Socrates
Socrates
the man almost disappears after this time, but there is a noticeable preference for Plato
Plato
or Aristotle
Aristotle
over the elements of Socratic philosophy distinct from those of his students, even into the Middle Ages. Some modern scholarship holds that, with so much of his own thought obscured and possibly altered by Plato, it is impossible to gain a clear picture of Socrates
Socrates
amid all the contradictory evidence. That both Cynicism and Stoicism, which carried heavy influence from Socratic thought, were unlike or even contrary to Platonism
Platonism
further illustrates this. The ambiguity and lack of reliability serves as the modern basis of criticism—that it is nearly impossible to know the real Socrates. Some controversy also exists about Socrates' attitude towards homosexuality[147] and as to whether or not he believed in the Olympian gods, was monotheistic, or held some other religious viewpoint.[148] However, it is still commonly taught and held with little exception that Socrates
Socrates
is the progenitor of subsequent Western philosophy, to the point that philosophers before him are referred to as pre-Socratic. In literature

Socrates
Socrates
is a major character in Mary Renault's historical novel The Last of the Wine. The book's protagonists, Alexias and Lysis, study under him in Athens.[149] A humorous version of the deceased Socrates
Socrates
appears in John Kendrick Bangs's comic novel A House-Boat on the Styx
A House-Boat on the Styx
and its sequels.[150]

See also

Philosophy
Philosophy
portal

Codex Vaticanus Graecus 64 List of speakers in Plato's dialogues Xanthippe
Xanthippe
(wife of Socrates) Myrto
Myrto
(second wife of Socrates, according to some accounts) De genio Socratis

Notes

^ Kraut, Richard (August 16, 2017). "Socrates". Encyclopedia Britannica. Encyclopedia Britannica, Inc. Retrieved 20 November 2017.  ^ Jones, Daniel; Roach, Peter, James Hartman and Jane Setter, eds. Cambridge English Pronouncing Dictionary. 17th edition. Cambridge UP, 2006. ^ Easterling, P. E. (1997). The Cambridge Companion to Greek Tragedy. Cambridge University Press. p. 352. ISBN 0521423511. Retrieved 19 November 2017.  ^ Smith, Nicholas D.; Woodruff, Paul (16 November 2000). Reason and Religion in Socratic Philosophy. Oxford University Press. p. 154. ISBN 0195350928. Retrieved 19 November 2017. 469 or 468 (corresponding to the fourth year of the 77th Olympiad), according to Apollodorus...But the year of Socrates' birth is probably only an inference from... Plato
Plato
[who] has Socrates
Socrates
casually describe himself as having lived seventy years.  ^ James Rachels, The Legacy of Socrates: Essays in Moral Philosophy Columbia University Press, 2007 ISBN 023113844X Accessed November 24th, 2017 ^ Gregory Vlastos (1991). Socrates, Ironist and Moral Philosopher. Cornell University Press. p. 43. ISBN 978-0-8014-9787-2.  ^ Moral Philosophy
Philosophy
- The Discovery of Ethics : Socrates
Socrates
Jacques Maritain Center Accessed November 24th, 2017 ^ Peter Singer
Peter Singer
(1985) - Encyclopædia Britannica
Encyclopædia Britannica
Chicago, 1985, pp. 627-648 Accessed November 24th, 2017 ^ Anne Rooney - The Story of Philosophy: From Ancient Greeks to Great Thinkers of Modern Times(search page) Arcturus Publishing, 6 January 2014 ISBN 1782129952 Accessed November 24th, 2017 ^ Charles H. Kahn (1998) - Ethics
Ethics
- p.42 Cambridge University Press
Cambridge University Press
4 May 1998 ISBN 0521388325 Accessed December 22nd, 2017 ^ Stern, T (2013) - Philosophy
Philosophy
and Theatre: An Introduction - ix Routledge
Routledge
2013 ISBN 1134575912 Accessed December 22nd, 2017 ^ Kofman, Sarah (1998). Socrates: Fictions of a Philosopher. p. 34. ISBN 0-8014-3551-X.  ^

...Socrates, of course, is the only of these philosophers who didn't write anything... S. Phineas Upham, Joshua
Joshua
Harlan - Philosophers in Conversation: Interviews from the Harvard Review of Philosophy
Philosophy
p.141 - Psychology Press 2002 ISBN 0415937787 ...The historical Socrates
Socrates
undoubtedly existed, but he did not write anything... J. S. McClelland A History of Western Political Thought p.19 Psychology Press 1996 ISBN 0415119618 ... Socrates
Socrates
is especially pure because he does not write. “Socrates was the West's greatest thinker insofar as he did not write anything... - M. Blitz, Ann Ward - Socrates: Reason or Unreason as the Foundation of European Identity p.221 Cambridge Scholars Publishing 2009 ISBN 1443808709 ...As Socrates
Socrates
did not write anything and assigned to the living word and to dialogue with his followers all of his thought, ... - Giovanni Reale, John R. Catan - A History of Ancient Philosophy
Philosophy
IV: The Schools of the Imperial Age p.75 SUNY Press
SUNY Press
1985 ISBN 0791401286 ... Socrates
Socrates
explains to Meno: “It is not because I myself am on the right track (euporon) that I leave others with no way out (aporein), but because ... This is why Socrates
Socrates
did not write anything; he had nothing to teach that could be fixed in writing... - Walter Kohan - Childhood, Education and Philosophy: New Ideas for an Old Relationship p.84 Routledge
Routledge
2014 ISBN 1317658450 ...They achieved renown precisely because they did not write at all. The vice of graphorrhoea was frequently contrasted with the virtue of such ancient philosophers as Pythagoras, Aristarchus, Favorinus and Socrates, who did not write anything ... - Sari Kivisto - The Vices of Learning: Morality and Knowledge at Early Modern Universities 106 BRILL 2014 ISBN 9004276459

^ C. Salutati in Renaissance
Renaissance
Debates on Rhetoric Cornell University Press, 2000 ISBN 0801482062 ^ Roberson, C. (8 December 2009). Ethics
Ethics
for Criminal Justice Professionals. CRC Press. p. 24. ISBN 1420086723.  ^ Rubel, A.; Vickers, M. (11 September 2014). Fear and Loathing in Ancient Athens: Religion and Politics During the Peloponnesian War. Routledge. p. 147. ISBN 1317544803.  ^ Dorion, Louis-André. The Rise and Fall of the Socratic Problem
Socratic Problem
(pp. 1–23) (The Cambridge Companion to Socrates). Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CCOL9780521833424.001. ISBN 9780521833424. Retrieved 2015-05-07.  ^ May, H. (2000). On Socrates. Wadsworth/Thomson Learning,. p. 20.  ^ catalogue of Harvard University Press
Harvard University Press
- Xenophon
Xenophon
Volume IV. Retrieved 2015-3-26. ^ Kahn, CH', Plato
Plato
and the Socratic Dialogue: The Philosophical Use of a Literary Form, Cambridge University Press, 1998, p. xvii. ^ Many other writers added to the fashion of Socratic dialogues (called Sokratikoi logoi) at the time. In addition to Plato
Plato
and Xenophon, each of the following is credited by some source as having added to the genre: Aeschines of Sphettus, Antisthenes, Aristippus, Bryson, Cebes, Crito, Euclid
Euclid
of Megara, and Phaedo. It is unlikely Plato
Plato
was the first in this field (Vlastos, p. 52). ^ Morrison, D.R. The Cambridge Companion to Socrates
Socrates
(p.xiv). Cambridge University Press, 2011, ISBN 0521833426. Retrieved 2015-04-16.  ^ Nails, D. Socrates:Socrates's strangeness. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Philosophy
(Spring 2014 Edition), Edward N. Zalta
Edward N. Zalta
(ed.). Retrieved 2015-04-16.  ^ a b c d D. El Murr (27 July 2016) - Biography Oxford Biographies DOI: 10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0211 Accessed November 20th, 2017 ^ Peter J. Ahrensdorf - The Death of Socrates
The Death of Socrates
and the Life of Philosophy: An Interpretation of Plato's Phaedo
Phaedo
p.17 SUNY Press, 14 September 1995 ISBN 0791426343 Accessed November 23, 2017 ^ CH Kahn, Plato
Plato
and the Socratic Dialogue: The Philosophical Use of a Literary Form (p. 75), Cambridge University Press, 1998, ISBN 0521648300. ^ Cohen, M., Philosophical Tales: Being an Alternative History Revealing the Characters, the Plots, and the Hidden Scenes That Make Up the True Story of Philosophy, John Wiley & Sons, 2008, p. 5, ISBN 1-4051-4037-2. ^ Socrates
Socrates
Behind the Name Accessed November 28th, 2017 ^ Google translation - Greek for Socrates
Socrates
Accessed November 28th, 2017 ^ D Nails Archived 2015-03-27 at the Wayback Machine., Agora, Academy, and the Conduct of Philosophy
Philosophy
(p. 9), Springer, 1995, ISBN 0792335430. ^ Ahbel-Rappe, S., Socrates: A Guide for the Perplexed (p. 2 and footnote 10 on pp. 157–8), A&C Black, 2009. ^ Bett, R. A Companion to Socrates
Socrates
(pp. 299-30). John Wiley & Sons, 2009, ISBN 1405192607. Retrieved 2015-04-17.  (A translation of one fragment reads: "But from them the sculptor, blatherer on the lawful, turned away. Spellbinder of the Greeks, who made them precise in language. Sneerer trained by rhetoroticians, sub-Attic ironist.") ^ Lieber, F. Encyclopedia Americana (pp. 266-7), published 1832 (original from Oxford University). ^ CS. Celenza (2001), Angelo Poliziano's Lamia: Text, Translation, and Introductory Studies (note 34), BRILL, 2010, ISBN 9004185909. ^ Ong, pp. 78–79. ^ a b Apollodorus (N. D. Smith, P. Woodruff) - Reason and Religion in Socratic Philosophy
Philosophy
p.154 Oxford University Press, 16th November 2000 ISBN 0195350928 Retrieved November 19th, 2017 ^ a b Apollodorus of Athens
Athens
Encyclopædia Britannica
Encyclopædia Britannica
Retrieved November 19th, 2017 ^ The Library of Apollodorus ( Delphi
Delphi
Classics) Delphi
Delphi
Classics, 13 February 2016 Accessed November 25th, 2017 ^ Andreas Willi, Theater
Theater
Outside Athens: Drama in Greek Sicily and South Italyp.56 Cambridge University Press, 2 August 2012 ISBN 0521761786 Accessed November 25th, 2017 ^ Cicero : in twenty-eight volumes. 20. De senectute, De amicitia, De divinatione Harvard University Press, 1923 Accessed November 25th, 2017 ^ Diogenes
Diogenes
Laertius Lives of Eminent Philosophers 2.5. Socrates
Socrates
DOI: 10.4159/DLCL.diogenes_laertius-lives_eminent_philosophers_book_ii_chapter_5_socrates.1925 Harvard University Press, Loeb Classics Library Accessed November 25th, 2017 sourced via William Musgrave Calder
William Musgrave Calder
- The Unknown Socrates: Translations, with Introductions and Notes, of Four Important Documents in the Late Antique Reception of Socrates
Socrates
the Athenian p.3 Bolchazy-Carducci Publishers, 2002 ISBN 0865164983 Accessed November 25th, 2017 ^ Diogenes
Diogenes
Laertius Translated by R. D. Hicks Loeb Classical Library 184 Harvard University Press
Harvard University Press
Accessed November 25th, 2017 ^ P.J. King, One Hundred Philosophers (p. 23), Zebra, 2006, ISBN 1770220011. ^ a b C. Gill (1973) - The Death of Socrates
The Death of Socrates
(p.27) Cambridge University Press : The Classical Quarterly Accessed November 23rd, 2017 ^ Kahn, Charles H. (2001) - Pythagoras
Pythagoras
and the Pythagoreans: A Brief History - p.4, Indianapolis, Indiana and Cambridge, England: Hackett Publishing Company, ISBN 978-0-87220-575-8 Accessed December 2nd, 2017 ^ A Brief History of the Pythagorean Theorem University of Illinois Urbana-Champaign Accessed December 2nd, 2017 - shows "569–500" ^ Pythagoras
Pythagoras
and his Theorem Università degli Studi di Firenze Accessed December 2nd, 2017 - shows "c.572–c.494" ^ L. Brisson (2007), Griechische Biographie in hellenistischer Zeit: Akten des internationalen Kongresses vom 26.-29. Juli 2006 in Würzburg - Aristoxenus: His Evidence on Pythagoras
Pythagoras
and the Pythagoreans. The case of Philolaus Walter de Gruyter, 2007 ISBN 3110195046 Accessed December 2nd, 2017 ^ Thomas Stewart Traill (1859), The Encyclopaedia Britannica: Or, Dictionary of Arts, Sciences, and General Literature, Volume 18 - p.710 Little, Brown, & Company, 1859 Accessed December 2nd, 2017 ^ Sir Thomas Heath, Aristarchus of Samos: The Ancient Copernicus (Chapter IX (page first) Courier Corporation, 9 December 2004 ISBN 0486438864 Accessed November 24th, 2017 "assume" ^ Linda Pound, Quick Guides for Early Years: Cognitive Development Profile: Socrates
Socrates
Hachette UK, 26 April 2013 ISBN 144419965X Accessed November 24th, 2017 ^ John Burnet, Platonism
Platonism
[1] Edicions Enoanda, 19 July 2014, Classical Sather Lectures. California 1928, Accessed November 24th, 2017 ^ B. Hudson McLean, The Cursed Christ: Mediterranean Expulsion Rituals and Pauline Soteriologyp.91 A&C Black, 1996 ISBN 1850755892, Accessed November 24th, 2017 ^ P. E. Easterling, The Cambridge Companion to Greek Tragedy, p. 352 Cambridge University Press, 1997 ISBN 0521423511 Retrieved November 19th, 2017 ^ Encyclopædia Britannica
Encyclopædia Britannica
Eleventh Edition ^ G.W.F. Hegel
G.W.F. Hegel
(trans. Frances H. Simon), Lectures on History of Philosophy ^ a b Nails, D., "Socrates" - A Chronology of the historical Socrates in the context of Athenian history and the dramatic dates of Plato's dialogues, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Philosophy
(Spring 2014 Edition), Edward N. Zalta
Edward N. Zalta
(ed.). Retrieved 2015-04-17. ^ Howatson, M.C. (2013). The Oxford Companion to Classical Literature (reprint, 3rd ed.). Oxford University Press. p. 528. ISBN 0199548552.  ^ Plato
Plato
(1999) [1921]. Theaetetus. Translated by Fowler, Harold N. (reprint of London, William Heinemann Ltd. ed.). Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University Press. p. 149a.  ^ A Grafton, GW Most, Settis, S., The Classical Tradition Harvard University Press, 2010, ISBN 0674035720. ^ "Plato, ''Phaedo'' 116b". Perseus.tufts.edu. Retrieved 2012-08-19.  ^ The ancient tradition is attested in Pausanias, 1.22.8; for a modern denial, see Kleine Pauly, "Sokrates" 7; the tradition is a confusion with the sculptor, Socrates
Socrates
of Thebes, mentioned in Pausanias 9.25.3, a contemporary of Pindar. ^ Xen. Mem. 4.2.1. ^ J. Sellars, (2003), Simon the Shoemaker and the Problem of Socrates. Classical Philology 98, 207–216. ^ Colaiaco, J.A. Socrates
Socrates
Against Athens: Philosophy
Philosophy
on Trial. Routledge, 2013, ISBN 1135024936. Retrieved 2015-04-17.  ^ Monoson, S.S., Meineck, P., Konstan, D., Combat Trauma and the Ancient Greeks (p. 136), Palgrave Macmillan, 2014, ISBN 1137398868. ^ Iain King
Iain King
details Socrates' military service, including how it may have affected his ideas, in Socrates
Socrates
at War (article), accessed 2014-03-21. ^ Ober, J., Political Dissent in Democratic Athens: Intellectual Critics of Popular Rule (p. 184 - footnote 54), Martin Classical Lectures, Princeton University Press, 2001, ISBN 0691089817. ^ Plato
Plato
(2015). Introductory Readings in Ancient Greek
Ancient Greek
and Roman Philosophy
Philosophy
(p. 72). Miller, PL.: Hackett Publishing. ISBN 1624663540. Retrieved 2015-04-17.  ^ Dillon, M., Garland, L., Ancient Greece: Social and Historical Documents from Archaic Times to the Death of Alexander (p. 119), Routledge, 2010, ISBN 1136991387 (revised). ^ Garland, L., Ancient Greece: Social and Historical Documents from Archaic Times to the Death of Socrates
Socrates
(p. 321), Routledge, 2005, ISBN 113460372X. ^ C Tuplin, V Azoulay, Xenophon
Xenophon
and His World: Papers from a Conference Held in Liverpool in July 1999 (p. 379, footnote 92), Geschichte, Franz Steiner Verlag, 2004, ISBN 3515083928. ^ Larcher, P.H. (1829). Larcher's Notes on Herodotus: Historical and Critical Remarks on the Nine Books of the History of Herodotus, with a Chronological Table. 2. John R. Priestley. p. 330. Retrieved 2015-04-18.  ^ a b Munn, Henderson. The School of History: Athens
Athens
in the Age of Socrates
Socrates
(p. 186). University of California Press, 2000 ISBN 0520929713. Retrieved 2015-04-18.  ^ Hayek, FA. Law, Legislation and Liberty, Volume 3: The Political Order of a Free People. ISBN 0226321266. Retrieved 2015-04-18.  ^ Harris, E.M. The Rule of Law in Action in Democratic Athens. Oxford University Press, 2013, ISBN 0199899169. Retrieved 2015-04-18.  ^ Pangle, T.L. The Laws of Plato. University of Chicago Press, 1988 (reprint), ISBN 0226671100. p. 511. Retrieved 2015-04-18.  ^ Ober, J. in Morrisson, D.R. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Socrates
Socrates
Cambridge University Press, 2011, pp. 167–169. ISBN 0521833426. ^ LD LeCaire, Tyranny and Terror:The Failure of Athenian Democracy
Democracy
and the Reign of the Thirty Tyrants. Eastern Washington University. Spring 2013. ^ Smith, W. (1852). The Apology of Socrates, the Crito, and Part of the Phaedo: With Notes from Stallbaum, Schleiermacher's Introductions, A Life of Socrates, and Schleiermacher's Essay on the Worth of Socrates
Socrates
as a Philosopher. Taylor Walton and Maberly. p. ciii note 1.  ^ Wilson, Emily R. (2007). The Death of Socrates. Harvard University Press. p. 55.  ^ Here it is telling to refer to Thucydides
Thucydides
(3.82.8): "Reckless audacity came to be considered the courage of a loyal ally; prudent hesitation, specious cowardice; moderation was held to be a cloak for unmanliness; ability to see all sides of a question inaptness to act on any. Frantic violence, became the attribute of manliness; cautious plotting, a justifiable means of self-defense. The advocate of extreme measures was always trustworthy; his opponent a man to be suspected." ^ a b Waterfield, Robin (2009). Why Socrates
Socrates
Died: Dispelling the Myths. New York: W.W. Norton and Company.  ^ Brun (1978). ^ M.F. Burnyeat (1997), The Impiety of Socrates
Socrates
Mathesis publications ; Ancient Philosophy
Philosophy
17 Accessed November 23rd, 2017 ^ Debra Nails, A Companion to Greek and Roman Political Thought Chapter 21 - The Trial and Death of Socrates
Socrates
John Wiley & Sons, 21 December 2012 ISBN 1118556682 Accessed November 23, 2017 ^ Plato. Apology, 24–27. ^ Fallon, Warren J. (2001). "Socratic suicide." PMID 19681231. US National Library of Medicine. National Institutes of Health. 121:91–106. Retrieved September 12, 2013. ^ Linder, Doug (2002). "The Trial of Socrates". University of Missouri–Kansas City School of Law. Retrieved September 12, 2013. ^ " Socrates
Socrates
(Greek philosopher)". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved September 12, 2013. ^ R. G. Frey (January 1978). Did Socrates
Socrates
Commit Suicide?. Philosophy, Volume 53, Issue 203, pp 106–108. University of Liverpool. doi:10.1017/S0031819100016375 ^ C. Gill (1973), "The Death of Socrates" Cambridge University Press: The Classical Quarterly & Houston Community College, Accessed November 23rd, 2017 ^ C. Gill (1973), The Death of Socrates
The Death of Socrates
Cambridge University Press: The Classical Quarterly Accessed November 23rd, 2017 ^ http://www.sparknotes.com/philosophy/phaedo/section3.rhtml ^ Laurel A. Madison (2002), “Have We Been Careless with Socrates’ Last Words? A Rereading of the Phaedo” Journal of the History of Philosophy
Philosophy
Wilson Quarterly Archives Accessed November 23rd, 2017 ^ Socrates
Socrates
and Platon (translated by Benjamin Jowett), excerpt of Phaedo
Phaedo
"And the true philosophers, and they only, study and are eager to release the soul" ^ a b J. Crooks, Socrates' Last Words: Another Look at an Ancient Riddle Cambridge University Press
Cambridge University Press
on behalf of The Classical Association, The Classical Quarterly Vol. 48, No. 1 (1998), pp. 117–125 Accessed November 23rd, 2017 ^ Ancient Greek: «ὦ Κρίτων, ἔφη, τῷ Ἀσκληπιῷ ὀφείλομεν ἀλεκτρυόνα· ἀλλὰ ἀπόδοτε καὶ μὴ ἀμελήσητε», as found in Plato's Phaedo. ^ Laurel A. Madison, "Have We Been Careless with Socrates' Last Words? A Rereading of the Phaedo", Wilson Quarterly Archives, Accessed November 23rd, 2017 ^ Allen, R.E. (1981). Socrates
Socrates
and Legal Obligation. U of Minnesota Press. pp. 65–96.  ^ Weiss, R. (1998). Socrates
Socrates
Dissatisfied: An Analysis of Plato's Crito. Oxford University Press. p. 85.  ^ Enid Bloch, Hemlock poisoning and the death of Socrates: did Plato tell the truth? January 2001 Accessed November 23rd, 2017 ^ R.G. Frey (1978), Did Socrates
Socrates
commit suicide? Cambridge University Press : Royal Institute of Philosophy
Philosophy
Philosophy
Philosophy
Volume 53 No. 203 Accessed November 23rd, 2017 ^ Rahman Haghighat (2014) - Historical Memories in Culture, Politics and the Future: The Making of History and the World to Come p.103 Peter Lang, 14 January 2014 Accessed ISBN 3034317468 November 25th, 2017 ^ "The Decline of the Socratic Method
Socratic Method
at Harvard 78 Nebraska Law Review 1999". heinonline.org. Retrieved 2016-11-26.  ^ Popper, K. (1962) The Open Society and its Enemies, Volume 1 Plato, London, Routledge
Routledge
& Kegan Paul, p133. ^ Hadot, P. (1995) Philosophy
Philosophy
as a Way of Life, Oxford, Blackwells, p. 93. ^ Cohn, Dorrit (2001). "Does Socrates
Socrates
Speak for Plato? Reflections on an Open Question". New Literary History. 32 (3): 485–500. doi:10.1353/nlh.2001.0030. ISSN 1080-661X.  ^ Plato, Republic 336c and 337a, Theaetetus 150c, Apology 23a; Xenophon, Memorabilia 4.4.9; Aristotle, Sophistical Refutations 183b7. ^ Long, AA., in Ahbel-Rappe, S.; Kamtekar, R. (2009). A Companion to Socrates. John Wiley & Sons. p. 59.  ^ Plato, Menexenus
Menexenus
235e ^ Anton, John P. (1983). ""The Socratic Problem: Some Second Thoughts" by Eric A. Havelock". Essays in Ancient Greek
Ancient Greek
Philosophy
Philosophy
Volume Two. Albany, New York USA: SUNY Press. pp. 147–173. ISBN 0-87395-623-0.  ^ p. 14, Terence Irwin, The Development of Ethics, vol. 1, Oxford University Press 2007; p. 147, Gerasimos Santas, "The Socratic Paradoxes", Philosophical Review 73 (1964), pp. 147–64. ^ Apology of Socrates
Socrates
21d. ^ Plato, Apology 21d; A. Andrea, J Overfield, The Human Record: Sources of Global History, Volume I: To 1500 (p. 116), Cengage Learning, 2015, ISBN 1305537467. ^ Oxford English Dictionary, Etymology for phronesis. "ϕρόνησις thought, sense, judgement, practical wisdom, prudence". ^ T Engberg-Pedersen, Aristotle's Theory of Moral Insight (p. 236), Oxford University Press, 1983, ISBN 0198246676. ^ Amélie Rorty, Essays on Aristotle's Ethics
Ethics
(p. 267), University of California Press, 1980, ISBN 0520040414 ^ Reeve, C. D. C., Plato
Plato
on Love, Hackett Publishing, 2006, pp. xix–xx, ISBN 1603844066. ^ G Rudebusch, Socrates, John Wiley & Sons, 2011, ISBN 1444358707. ^ D P Verene, Speculative Philosophy
Philosophy
(p. 19), Lexington Books, 2009, ISBN 0739136615. ^ Boys-Stones, G., Rowe, C., The Circle of Socrates: Readings in the First-Generation Socratics, Hackett Publishing, 2013, pp. 173-175. ^ Vander Waerdt, PA., The Socratic Movement, Cornell University Press, 1994, pp. 200-202. ^ Plato, Theaetetus. ^ Guthrie, WKC., Socrates, Cambridge University Press, 1971, p. 126. ^ Brickhouse, TC.; Smith, N.D. (1990). Socrates
Socrates
on Trial. Oxford University Press. p. 165.  ^ Nichols, M.P. (1987). Socrates
Socrates
and the Political Community: An Ancient Debate. SUNY Press. p. 67.  ^ Duignan, B. (2009). The 100 Most Influential Philosophers of All Time. The Rosen Publishing Group. p. 33.  ^ Attributed to "Solomon" in 100 Most Influential People of All Times for Smartphones and Mobile Devices. Mobile Reference. 2007.  ^ Kagen (1978). ^ Irvine, Andrew D. "Introduction," Socrates
Socrates
on Trial, Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2008, p. 19. ^ McPherran, M.L. (1998). The Religion of Socrates. Penn State Press. p. 268.  ^ Olympiodorus the Younger, Life of Plato, in The Works of Plato: A New and Literal Version Chiefly from the Text of Stallbaum, p. 234, Bohm, 1854. ^ Leudar, I.; Thomas, P. (2013). "1". Voices of Reason, Voices of Insanity: Studies of Verbal Hallucinations. Routledge.  ^ a b J. Mikalson (June 2010). Greek Popular Religion in Greek Philosophy. OUP Oxford. p. 123. ISBN 019161467X. Retrieved 2015-12-16.  ^ Khan, C.H. (1998). Plato
Plato
and the Socratic Dialogue: The Philosophical Use of a Literary Form. Cambridge University Press.  ^ Morrison, D.R. (2011). "1". The Cambridge Companion to Socrates. Cambridge University Press.  ^ Ahbel-Rappe, S.; Kamtekar, R. (2009). A Companion to Socrates. John Wiley & Sons. pp. 306–309.  ^ Magee, B (2000). The Great Philosophers: An Introduction to Western Philosophy. Oxford University Press. p. 34.  ^ Carruccio, E. (2006). Mathematics And Logic in History And in Contemporary Thought. Transaction Publishers. p. 44.  ^ Long, A.A. (1996). Stoic Studies. Cambridge University Press. pp. 31–32.  ^ Hughes, Bettany (2011). The Hemlock Cup: Socrates, Athens
Athens
and the Search for the Good Life. Knopf Doubleday Publishing Group.  ^ von Dehsen, C. (2013). Philosophers and Religious Leaders. Routledge.  ^ Ahbel-Rappe, S.; Kamtekar, R. (2009). A Companion to Socrates. John Wiley & Sons. pp. xix–xx.  ^ Wilson, E.R. (2007). The Death of Socrates: Hero, Villain, Chatterbox, Saint. Profile Books. pp. 61–62.  ^ Danzig, G. (2010). Apologizing for Socrates: How Plato
Plato
and Xenophon Created Our Socrates. Lexington Books. pp. 66–67.  ^ W. K. C. Guthrie, Socrates, Cambridge University Press, 1971, p. 70. ^ A.A. Long "How Does Socrates' Divine Sign Communicate with Him?", Chapter 5 in: A Companion to Socrates, John Wiley & Sons, 2009, p. 63. ^ Gomez, Alex (July 10, 2010). "Mary Renault's 'The Last of the Wine' Reviewed". Banderas News. Retrieved 2014-10-14.  ^ Bangs, John Kendrick (1901). A House-Boat on the Styx. Harper & Bros. pp. 164–170. Retrieved 2014-10-14. 

References

Brun, Jean (1978). Socrate
Socrate
(sixth edition). Presses universitaires de France. pp. 39–40. ISBN 2-13-035620-6.  (in French) May, Hope (2000). On Socrates. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth. ISBN 0-534-57604-4.  Ong, Walter (2002). Orality and Literacy. New York: Routledge. ISBN 0-415-28129-6.  Kagan, Donald. The Fall of the Athenian Empire. First. Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press, 1987. Pausanias, Description of Greece. W. H. S. Jones (translator). Loeb Classical Library. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; London, William Heinemann Ltd. (1918). Vol. 1. Books I–II: ISBN 0-674-99104-4. Vol. 4. Books VIII.22–X: ISBN 0-674-99328-4. Thucydides; The Peloponnesian War. London, J. M. Dent; New York, E. P. Dutton. 1910.  Vlastos, Gregory (1991). Socrates, Ironist and Moral Philosopher. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. ISBN 0-8014-9787-6.  Bernas, Richard, cond. Socrate. By Erik Satie. LTM/Boutique, 2006 Bruell, C (1994). "On Plato's Political Philosophy". Review of Politics. 56: 261–82. doi:10.1017/s003467050001843x.  Bruell, C. (1999). On the Socratic Education: An Introduction to the Shorter Platonic Dialogues, Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield. Grube, G.M.A. (2002). "Plato, Five Dialogues". Hackett Publishing Company, Inc. Hanson, V.D. (2001). " Socrates
Socrates
Dies at Delium, 424 B.C.", What If? 2, Robert Cowley, editor, G.P. Putnam's Sons, NY. Irvine, Andrew David (2008). Socrates
Socrates
on Trial: A play based on Aristophanes' Clouds and Plato's Apology, Crito, and Phaedo, adapted for modern performance. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.  ISBN 978-0-8020-9783-5 (cloth); ISBN 978-0-8020-9538-1 (paper); ISBN 978-1-4426-9254-1 (e-pub) Kamtekar, Rachana (2004). Plato's Euthyphro, Apology, and Crito: Critical Essays. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield. ISBN 0-7425-3325-5.  Kierkegaard, Søren (1968). The Concept of Irony: with Constant Reference to Socrates. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. ISBN 978-0-253-20111-9.  Levinson, Paul (2007). The Plot to Save Socrates. New York: Tor Books. ISBN 0-7653-1197-6.  Luce, J.V. (1992). An Introduction to Greek Philosophy, Thames & Hudson, NY. Maritain, J. (1930, 1991). Introduction to Philosophy, Christian Classics, Inc., Westminster, MD. Robinson, R (1953). Plato's Earlier Dialectic. Oxford: Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-824777-7.  Ch. 2: "Elenchus", Ch. 3: "Elenchus: Direct and Indirect" Taylor, C.C.W., Hare, R.M. & Barnes, J. (1998). Greek Philosophers – Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle, Oxford University Press, NY. Taylor, C.C.W. (2001). Socrates: A very short introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

External links

Find more aboutSocratesat's sister projects

Media from Wikimedia Commons Quotations from Wikiquote Texts from Wikisource Data from Wikidata

Socrates
Socrates
at Curlie (based on DMOZ) Nails, Debra. "Socrates". In Zalta, Edward N. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.  Ambury, James M. "Socrates". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.  Socrates
Socrates
at the Indiana Philosophy
Philosophy
Ontology Project Socrates
Socrates
on In Our Time at the BBC. Greek Philosophy: Socrates Original Fresque of Socrates
Socrates
in Archaeological Museum of Ephesus Socrates
Socrates
Narrates Plato's The Republic Project Gutenberg
Project Gutenberg
e-texts on Socrates, amongst others:

The Dialogues of Plato
Plato
(see also articles on Dialogues by Plato) The writings of Xenophon, such as the Memorablia and Hellenica. The satirical plays by Aristophanes Aristotle's writings Voltaire's Socrates

A free audiobook of the Socratic dialogue
Socratic dialogue
Euthyphro
Euthyphro
at LibriVox

v t e

Socrates

General

Trial of Socrates

Legacy

Socratic dialogue Socratic method Socratic problem Socratic questioning Socratici viri

Phrases

"I know that I know nothing" "The unexamined life is not worth living"

Related

Euthyphro
Euthyphro
dilemma Form of the Good Peritrope Religious skepticism Social gadfly

Family

Sophroniscus (father) Phaenarete
Phaenarete
(mother) Xanthippe
Xanthippe
(wife) Lamprocles
Lamprocles
(son) Menexenus
Menexenus
(son) Myrto
Myrto
(wife)

Works about Socrates

Art

Double Herm of Socrates and Seneca
Double Herm of Socrates and Seneca
(3rd century sculpture) The Death of Socrates
The Death of Socrates
(1787 painting) Socrates
Socrates
(1950 sculpture)

Stage

The Clouds
The Clouds
(423 BC play) Der geduldige Socrates
Der geduldige Socrates
(1721 opera) Socrates
Socrates
(1759 play) Socrate
Socrate
(1919 oratorio) Socrates on Trial
Socrates on Trial
(2007 play)

Literature

De genio Socratis
De genio Socratis
(1st century essay) On the Concept of Irony with Continual Reference to Socrates
On the Concept of Irony with Continual Reference to Socrates
(1841 thesis) The Plot to Save Socrates
The Plot to Save Socrates
(2006 novel)

Other

Barefoot in Athens
Athens
(1966 film) Socrates
Socrates
(1971 film)

Dialogues

Plato

Apology Axiochus Charmides Clitophon Cratylus Critias Crito Demodocus Epinomis Eryxias Euthydemus Euthyphro First Alcibiades Gorgias Hipparchus Hippias Major Hippias Minor Ion Laches Laws Lysis Menexenus Meno Minos On Justice On Virtue Parmenides Phaedo Phaedrus Philebus Protagoras Republic Rival Lovers Second Alcibiades Sisyphus Sophist Statesman Symposium Theaetetus Theages Timaeus

Xenophon

Apology Memorabilia Oeconomicus Symposium

Other

Halcyon

v t e

Ancient Greek
Ancient Greek
schools of philosophy

Pre-Socratic

Schools

Atomism Eleatics Ionian

Ephesian Milesian

Pluralism Pythagoreanism Sophistic

Philosophers

Anaxagoras Anaximander Anaximenes Democritus Empedocles Heraclitus Leucippus Melissus Parmenides Protagoras Pythagoras Thales Zeno of Elea

Socratic

Schools

Cynicism Cyrenaics Eretrian school Megarian school Peripateticism Platonism

Philosophers

Antisthenes Aristippus Aristotle Diogenes
Diogenes
of Sinope Euclid
Euclid
of Megara Phaedo
Phaedo
of Elis Plato Socrates

Hellenistic

Schools

Epicureanism Neoplatonism Neopythagoreanism Pyrrhonism Stoicism

Philosophers

Apollonius of Tyana Augustine Epictetus Epicurus John Philoponus Lucretius Plotinus Proclus Pyrrho Sextus Empiricus Zeno of Citium

v t e

Ancient Greece

Outline Timeline

History Geography

Periods

Cycladic civilization Minoan civilization Mycenaean civilization Greek Dark Ages Archaic period Classical Greece Hellenistic Greece Roman Greece

Geography

Aegean Sea Aeolis Alexandria Antioch Cappadocia Crete Cyprus Doris Ephesus Epirus Hellespont Ionia Ionian Sea Macedonia Magna Graecia Miletus Peloponnesus Pergamon Pontus Taurica Ancient Greek
Ancient Greek
colonies

City states Politics Military

City states

Argos Athens Byzantion Chalcis Corinth Eretria Kerkyra Larissa Megalopolis Megara Rhodes Samos Sparta Syracuse Thebes

Politics

Boeotarch Boule Koinon Proxeny Strategos Tagus Tyrant Amphictyonic League

Athenian

Agora Areopagus Ecclesia Graphē paranómōn Heliaia Ostracism

Spartan

Apella Ephor Gerousia Harmost

Macedon

Synedrion Koinon

Military

Wars Athenian military Antigonid Macedonian army Army of Macedon Ballista Cretan archers Hellenistic armies Hippeis Hoplite Hetairoi Macedonian phalanx Phalanx Peltast Pezhetairos Sarissa Sacred Band of Thebes Sciritae Seleucid army Spartan army Toxotai Xiphos Xyston

People

List of ancient Greeks

Rulers

Kings of Argos Archons of Athens Kings of Athens Kings of Commagene Diadochi Kings of Lydia Kings of Macedonia Kings of Paionia Attalid kings of Pergamon Kings of Pontus Kings of Sparta Tyrants of Syracuse

Philosophers

Anaxagoras Anaximander Anaximenes Antisthenes Aristotle Democritus Diogenes
Diogenes
of Sinope Empedocles Epicurus Gorgias Heraclitus Hypatia Leucippus Parmenides Plato Protagoras Pythagoras Socrates Thales Zeno

Authors

Aeschylus Aesop Alcaeus Archilochus Aristophanes Bacchylides Euripides Herodotus Hesiod Hipponax Homer Ibycus Lucian Menander Mimnermus Panyassis Philocles Pindar Plutarch Polybius Sappho Simonides Sophocles Stesichorus Theognis Thucydides Timocreon Tyrtaeus Xenophon

Others

Agesilaus II Agis II Alcibiades Alexander the Great Aratus Archimedes Aspasia Demosthenes Epaminondas Euclid Hipparchus Hippocrates Leonidas Lycurgus Lysander Milo of Croton Miltiades Pausanias Pericles Philip of Macedon Philopoemen Praxiteles Ptolemy Pyrrhus Solon Themistocles

Groups

Philosophers Playwrights Poets Tyrants

By culture

Ancient Greek
Ancient Greek
tribes Thracian Greeks Ancient Macedonians

Society Culture

Society

Agriculture Calendar Clothing Coinage Cuisine Economy Education Festivals Funeral and burial practices Homosexuality Law Olympic Games Pederasty Philosophy Prostitution Religion Slavery Warfare Wedding customs Wine

Arts and science

Architecture

Greek Revival architecture

Astronomy Literature Mathematics Medicine Music

Musical system

Pottery Sculpture Technology Theatre

Religion

Funeral and burial practices Mythology

mythological figures

Temple Twelve Olympians Underworld

Sacred places

Eleusis Delphi Delos Dodona Mount Olympus Olympia

Structures

Athenian Treasury Lion Gate Long Walls Philippeion Theatre of Dionysus Tunnel of Eupalinos

Temples

Aphaea Artemis Athena Nike Erechtheion Hephaestus Hera, Olympia Parthenon Samothrace Zeus, Olympia

Language

Proto-Greek Mycenaean Homeric Dialects

Aeolic Arcadocypriot Attic Doric Ionic Locrian Macedonian Pamphylian

Koine

Writing

Linear A Linear B Cypriot syllabary Greek alphabet Greek numerals Attic numerals

Lists

Cities

in Epirus

People Place names Stoae Temples Theatres

Category Portal

v t e

Criticism of religion

By religion

Bahá'í Faith Buddhism Christianity

Catholic

Opus Dei

Jehovah's Witnesses Latter Day Saint movement Protestantism Seventh-day Adventist Unification Church Westboro Baptist Church

Hinduism Islam

Islamism Twelver Shia Islam Wahhabism

Jainism Judaism Monotheism New religious movement Scientology Sikhism Yazdânism Zoroastrianism

Religious texts

Bible Quran Hadiths Mormon sacred texts

Book of Mormon

Talmud

Religious figures

Aisha Charles Taze Russell Ellen White Jesus Moses Muhammad Mirza Ghulam Ahmad Saul

Religious violence

Buddhism Christianity

Mormonism

Judaism Islam Terrorism

Christian Hindu Islamic Jewish

Persecution

Christian thought on persecution and tolerance

War

In Islam In Judaism

Sectarian violence By country

India

Anti-Christian violence In Odisha

Nigeria Pakistan

Books

Atheist Manifesto Breaking the Spell: Religion as a Natural Phenomenon Christianity Unveiled God
God
in the Age of Science? God
God
Is Not Great God: The Failed Hypothesis Letter to a Christian Nation The Age of Reason The Blind Watchmaker The Caged Virgin The End of Faith The God
God
Delusion The Rage Against God Why I Am Not a Christian Why I Am Not a Muslim Books critical of Christianity Books critical of Islam

Movements

Agnosticism Antitheism Atheism Criticism of atheism Cārvāka New Atheism Nontheistic religions Parody religion

v t e

Extra-Quranic Prophets of Islam

In Stories of the Prophets

Enoch Eber Khidr Joshua Samuel Isaiah Jeremiah Ezekiel Ezra Daniel

In Islamic tradition

Seth Shem Eli Ahijah Shemaiah Iddo Hanani Jehu Micaiah Eliezer Zechariah ben Jehoiada Urijah Hananiah, Mishael, and Azariah Berechiah Samī Joel Amos Obadiah Micah Nahum Habakkuk Zephaniah Haggai Malachi Hanzalah Khaled bin Sinan

In Quranic exegesis

Abel Saduq, Masduq, and Shalum Hosea Zechariah, son of Berechiah

Authority control

WorldCat Identities VIAF: 88039167 LCCN: n79055329 ISNI: 0000 0001 2142 6535 GND: 118615270 SELIBR: 207179 SUDOC: 028260929 BNF: cb12013325j (data) BIBSYS: 90066833 ULAN: 500260248 NLA: 41606667 NDL: 00621489 NKC: jn2000072

.