HOME
ListMoto - Harm Principle


--- Advertisement ---



The harm principle holds that the actions of individuals should only interfere with the freedom of others to prevent harm to other individuals. John Stuart Mill
John Stuart Mill
articulated this principle in On Liberty, where he argued that, "The only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others."[1] An equivalent was earlier stated in France's Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen of 1789 as, " Liberty
Liberty
consists in the freedom to do everything which injures no one else; hence the exercise of the natural rights of each man has no limits except those which assure to the other members of the society the enjoyment of the same rights. These limits can only be determined by law."

Contents

1 Definition 2 The offense principle 3 Broader definitions of harm 4 Modern examples

4.1 The harm principle in US libertarianism

5 See also 6 References 7 Bibliography 8 External links

Definition[edit] The belief "that no one should be forcibly prevented from acting in any way he chooses provided his acts are not invasive of the free acts of others" has become one of the basic principles of libertarian politics.[2] While the phrase "harm principle" was not itself used until 1969[citation needed], the harm principle itself was first fully articulated by the English thinker John Stuart Mill
John Stuart Mill
(1806–1873) in the first chapter of On Liberty
Liberty
(1859),[1] where he argued that:

The object of this Essay is to assert one very simple principle, as entitled to govern absolutely the dealings of society with the individual in the way of compulsion and control, whether the means used be physical force in the form of legal penalties, or the moral coercion of public opinion. That principle is, that the sole end for which mankind are warranted, individually or collectively, in interfering with the liberty of action of any of their number, is self-protection. That the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others. His own good, either physical or moral, is not a sufficient warrant. He cannot rightfully be compelled to do or forbear because it will be better for him to do so, because it will make him happier, because, in the opinion of others, to do so would be wise, or even right... The only part of the conduct of anyone, for which he is amenable to society, is that which concerns others. In the part which merely concerns himself, his independence is, of right, absolute. Over himself, over his own body and mind, the individual is sovereign. — John Stuart Mill, [3]

Even if a self-regarding action results in harm to oneself, it is still beyond the sphere of justifiable state coercion. Harm
Harm
itself is not a non-moral concept. The infliction of harm upon another person is what makes an action wrong.[4] Harm
Harm
can also result from a failure to meet an obligation. Morality generates obligations. Duty may be exacted from a person in the same way as a debt, and it is part of the notion of duty that a person may be rightfully compelled to fulfil it.[3][4] The offense principle[edit] Mill's harm principle is distinct from the offense principle. The basis of comparison is that, in some cases, psychological or social harm may be comparable to physical harm. The difference is based on the assumption that offense may cause discomfort, but does not necessarily cause harm. Offense meets the harm principle only if it is a wrong and also causes harm.[citation needed] The harm principle states that the only actions that can be prevented are ones that create harm. In other words, a person can do whatever he wants as long as his actions do not harm others. If a person's actions only affect himself, then society, which includes the government, should not be able to stop a person from doing what he wants. This even includes actions that a person may do that would harm the person himself. However, we cannot just stop there and think that Mill makes things seem so simple, because he doesn't. If we were to stop our discussion of the harm principle at 'anyone can do whatever they want just so long as it doesn't affect anyone else,' problems arise. One such problem may be what to do with people who want to end their own life. Interestingly, Mill would actually say it would not be okay for this to happen.[citation needed] For this to make the most sense, we need to understand three important ideas that helped shape the harm principle. The first is that the harm principle comes from another principle called the principle of utility.[citation needed] The principle of utility states that people should only do those things that bring the greatest amount of happiness to the greatest number of people. So, if a person is trying to decide between two things, he should choose the option that makes the most people happy. The second idea is that Mill says there is a difference between harm and offense.[citation needed] Harm
Harm
is something that would injure the rights of someone else or set back important interests that benefit others. An example of harm would be assaulting someone, causing them injury. An offense, according to Mill, is something that we would say 'hurt our feelings.'[citation needed] These are less serious and should not be prevented, because what may hurt one person's feelings may not hurt another's, and so offenses are not universal. The third idea to understand is that it is very rare for an action to only affect the individual himself. Mill argues that no person is truly isolated from others and that most actions do affect other people in important ways. The ethical question as to what extent there should be constraints on free speech is often grounded in both the harm principle and the offense principle. If the exercise of free speech can be causally linked to violence or similar physical harm, it is constrained under the harm principle. Free speech
Free speech
actions such as burning a flag or holding controversial rallies usually fall under the offense principle instead, based on the corresponding question of what constitutes harm (or, alternately, weighing harm caused by limiting a freedom vs harm caused by the exercise of that freedom).[5] In the abstract, criminalizing all wrongs that cause harm makes the offense principle almost synonymous with the harm principle.[citation needed] However, the definition of what constitutes a wrong may change over time—such that harm may be caused by actions that were not considered wrongs at the time, and vice versa.[4][6] Broader definitions of harm[edit] In the same essay, Mill further explains the principle as a function of two maxims:

The maxims are, first, that the individual is not accountable to society for his actions, in so far as these concern the interests of no person but himself. Advice, instruction, persuasion, and avoidance by other people, if thought necessary by them for their own good, are the only measures by which society can justifiably express its dislike or disapprobation of his conduct. Secondly, that for such actions as are prejudicial to the interests of others, the individual is accountable, and may be subjected either to social or to legal punishments, if society is of opinion that the one or the other is requisite for its protection. (LV2)

The second of these maxims has become known as the social authority principle.[4] However, the second maxim also opens the question of broader definitions of harm, up to and including harm to the society. The concept of harm is not limited to harm to another individual but can be harm to individuals plurally, without specific definition of those individuals. This is an important principle for the purpose of determining harm that only manifests gradually over time—such that the resulting harm can be anticipated, but does not yet exist at the time that the action causing harm was taken. It also applies to other issues—which range from the right of an entity to discharge broadly polluting waste on private property, to broad questions of licensing, and even to the right of sedition. Modern examples[edit] The harm principle in US libertarianism[edit] The United States Libertarian Party includes a version of the harm principle as part of its official party platform. It states:

Criminal laws should be limited in their application to violations of the rights of others through force or fraud, or to deliberate actions that place others involuntarily at significant risk of harm. Therefore, we favor the repeal of all laws creating “crimes” without victims . . .[7]

See also[edit]

Classical liberalism Law of equal liberty Libertarianism Non-aggression principle Rule utilitarianism Wiccan Rede

References[edit]

^ a b "Freedom of Speech". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 17 April 2008. Retrieved 10 June 2013.  ^ Ronald Hamowy, The encyclopaedia of libertarianism, Sage, 2008, p. xxi, ISBN ^ a b John Stuart Mill
John Stuart Mill
(1859). On Liberty. Oxford University. pp. 21–22. Retrieved 2008-02-27.  ^ a b c d Menezes Oliveira, Jorge. " Harm
Harm
and Offence in Mill's Conception of Liberty" (PDF). University of Oxford. Retrieved 6 Jun 2012.  ^ Cohen-Almagor, Raphael (1993). " Harm
Harm
Principle, Offense Principle, and the Skokie Affair". 41 (3). Political Studies. Retrieved 6 Jun 2012.  ^ Simester, A.P.; von Hirsch, Andrew (2002). "Rethinking the Offense Principle". 8. Legal Theory. Retrieved 6 Jun 2012.  ^ "2016 Platform". Libertarian National Committee. 2016. Retrieved 25 February 2017. 

Bibliography[edit]

THE MORAL LIMITS OF THE CRIMINAL LAW. By Joel Feinberg. New York: Oxford University Press. VOLUME ONE: HARM TO OTHERS. 1984. VOLUME TWO: OFFENSE TO OTHERS. 1985. VOLUME THREE: HARM TO SELF. 1986. VOLUME FOUR: HARMLESS WRONGDOING. 1988.

External links[edit]

Baselines, at Legal Theory Blog.

v t e

Libertarianism

Origins

Age of Enlightenment Aristotelianism Classical liberalism Anarchism
Anarchism
(Individualist anarchism)

Concepts

Anti-authoritarianism Anti-statism Anti-war Autarchism Crypto-anarchism Dispute resolution organization Economic freedom Free market Free-market anarchism Free-market environmentalism Free trade Free will Freedom of contract Homestead principle Individualism Laissez-faire Free society Libertarian freedom of association Liberty Limited government Localism Marriage privatization Minarchism Mutualism Natural and legal rights Non-aggression principle Non-interventionism Non-voting Participatory economics Polycentric law Private defense agency Property Restorative justice Self-governance Self-ownership Spontaneous order Stateless society Tax resistance Title-transfer theory of contract Voluntarism Voluntary association Voluntary society Workers' self-management

Schools

Agorism Anarchism Autarchism Bleeding-heart libertarianism Christian libertarianism Collectivist anarchism Consequentialist libertarianism Free-market anarchism Fusionism Geolibertarianism Georgism Green anarchism Green libertarianism Individualist anarchism Insurrectionary anarchism Left-libertarianism Left-wing market anarchism Libertarian communism Libertarian Marxism Libertarian socialism Libertarian transhumanism Minarchism Mutualism Natural-rights libertarianism Paleolibertarianism Panarchism Right-libertarianism Social anarchism Voluntaryism

People

Mikhail Bakunin Frédéric Bastiat Walter Block Murray Bookchin Jason Brennan Bryan Caplan Frank Chodorov Noam Chomsky Calvin Coolidge Voltairine de Cleyre Étienne de La Boétie Gustave de Molinari Joseph Déjacque Ralph Waldo Emerson David D. Friedman Milton Friedman Mahatma Gandhi Henry George William Godwin Emma Goldman Daniel Hannan Friedrich Hayek Auberon Herbert Karl Hess Thomas Hodgskin Hans-Hermann Hoppe Michael Huemer Penn Jillette Gary Johnson Samuel Edward Konkin III Rose Wilder Lane David Leyonhjelm Roderick T. Long Lord Acton Tibor Machan Wendy McElroy Ludwig von Mises Albert Jay Nock Robert Nozick Isabel Paterson Ron Paul Pierre-Joseph Proudhon Ralph Raico Ayn Rand Leonard Read Murray Rothbard Joseph Schumpeter Herbert Spencer Lysander Spooner Max Stirner John Stossel Thomas Szasz Henry David Thoreau Leo Tolstoy Benjamin Tucker Josiah Warren

Topics

Anarcho-capitalism
Anarcho-capitalism
and minarchism Criticisms Intellectual property Internal debates LGBT rights Objectivism Political parties Theories of law

Books

Anarchy, State, and Utopia Atlas Shrugged For a New Liberty: The Libertarian Manifesto Free to Choose Law, Legislation and Liberty The Market for Liberty

Related

Center for Libertarian Studies Anti-fascism Anti-communism Anti-socialism Anti-collectivism Anti-nationalism Austro-libertarianism Civil libertarianism Constitutionalism Fusionism Green libertarianism Libertarian conservatism Libertarian socialism Libertarian Democrat Libertarian Republican Libertarian science fiction Libertarianism
Libertarianism
in the United States Market liberalism Objectivism Public choice theory Small government Technolibertarianism

Outline of libertarianism Lib

.